Lattice approach: Difference between revisions
TobiasFritz (talk | contribs) No edit summary |
TobiasFritz (talk | contribs) adding more basic material |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
This is an approach to proving (weak) FUNC in the lattice formulation by distinguishing various regimes of lattices. Let <math>\mathcal{A}</math> be a finite lattice containing <math>m</math> join-irreducibles, and write <math>n=|\mathcal{A}|</math>. | This is an approach to proving (weak) FUNC in the lattice formulation by distinguishing various regimes of lattices. Let <math>\mathcal{A}</math> be a finite lattice containing <math>m</math> join-irreducibles, and write <math>n=|\mathcal{A}|</math>. | ||
== Reduction to atomistic lattices == | |||
'''Lemma:'''' weak FUNC holds for all lattices if and only if it holds for atomistic lattices. | |||
'''Proof:''' | |||
Hence we assume wlog that $\mathcal{A}$ is atomistic. | |||
== Easy lattice classes == | |||
'''Proposition:''' If atomistic $\mathcal{A}$ has a prime element, then $\mathcal{A}$ satisfies FUNC. | |||
'''Proof:''' Let $P$ be the prime element. The claim follows if the map $\mathcal{A}\setminus\uparrow\{P\}\to \uparrow\{P\}$ given by $A\mapsto A\vee P$ is surjective. Write any given $B\in\uparrow\{P\}$ as a join of join-irreducibles. Since $P$ is prime, $P$ must be below one of these join-irreducibles; but by atomicity, such a join-irreducible must be equal to $P$. Again by atomicity, the remaining factors are not in $\uparrow\{P\}$, and hence neither is their join. This join is the desired preimage of $B$ under $A\mapsto A\vee P$. | |||
'''Proposition ([http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/0097316592900686 Poonen]):''' If every interval $\downarrow\{A\}$ is complemented, then $\mathcal{A}$ satisfies FUNC. | |||
'''Proof:''' In this case, ''any'' join-irreducible $J$ is rare, since the map $\mathcal{A}\setminus\uparrow\{J\}\to\uparrow\{J\}$ given by $A\mapsto A\vee J$ is surjective: the complement of $J$ in $\downarrow\{A\}$ is a preimage of $A\in\uparrow\{J\}$. | |||
== Knill's argument in lattice terms == | == Knill's argument in lattice terms == |
Revision as of 09:07, 13 March 2016
This is an approach to proving (weak) FUNC in the lattice formulation by distinguishing various regimes of lattices. Let [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] be a finite lattice containing [math]\displaystyle{ m }[/math] join-irreducibles, and write [math]\displaystyle{ n=|\mathcal{A}| }[/math].
Reduction to atomistic lattices
Lemma:' weak FUNC holds for all lattices if and only if it holds for atomistic lattices.
Proof:
Hence we assume wlog that $\mathcal{A}$ is atomistic.
Easy lattice classes
Proposition: If atomistic $\mathcal{A}$ has a prime element, then $\mathcal{A}$ satisfies FUNC.
Proof: Let $P$ be the prime element. The claim follows if the map $\mathcal{A}\setminus\uparrow\{P\}\to \uparrow\{P\}$ given by $A\mapsto A\vee P$ is surjective. Write any given $B\in\uparrow\{P\}$ as a join of join-irreducibles. Since $P$ is prime, $P$ must be below one of these join-irreducibles; but by atomicity, such a join-irreducible must be equal to $P$. Again by atomicity, the remaining factors are not in $\uparrow\{P\}$, and hence neither is their join. This join is the desired preimage of $B$ under $A\mapsto A\vee P$.
Proposition (Poonen): If every interval $\downarrow\{A\}$ is complemented, then $\mathcal{A}$ satisfies FUNC.
Proof: In this case, any join-irreducible $J$ is rare, since the map $\mathcal{A}\setminus\uparrow\{J\}\to\uparrow\{J\}$ given by $A\mapsto A\vee J$ is surjective: the complement of $J$ in $\downarrow\{A\}$ is a preimage of $A\in\uparrow\{J\}$.
Knill's argument in lattice terms
The following is a lattice-theoretic formulation of a small tightening of Knill's argument.
Proposition: Let [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J}\subseteq\mathcal{A} }[/math] be a set of join-irreducibles with [math]\displaystyle{ \bigvee \mathcal{J} = 1 }[/math] and minimal with this property. Then some member of [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J} }[/math] has abundance at most [math]\displaystyle{ 2^{|J|-1} + \frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|} }[/math].
Note that at the two extreme values [math]\displaystyle{ |J|=2 }[/math] or [math]\displaystyle{ |J|=\log_2(n) }[/math], this establishes an element of abundance at most [math]\displaystyle{ 1/2 }[/math]. Unless [math]\displaystyle{ J }[/math] is very close to the maximal value [math]\displaystyle{ \log_2(n) }[/math], the bound is only marginally better than Knill's original one, which is [math]\displaystyle{ n - \frac{n-1}{|J|} }[/math].
Proof: Let [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J} }[/math] be the Boolean algebra of subsets of the set [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J} }[/math]. Consider the map [math]\displaystyle{ \phi:\mathcal{A}\to\mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J} }[/math] given by [math]\displaystyle{ \phi(A):=\{J\in \mathcal{J}\:|\: J\leq A\} }[/math]. We claim that [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] is surjective. Indeed, for every [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{I}\subseteq\mathcal{J} }[/math] we have [math]\displaystyle{ \phi\left(\bigvee \mathcal{I}\right) = \mathcal{I} }[/math]; for if [math]\displaystyle{ \phi\left(\bigvee \mathcal{I} \right) }[/math] was larger, then [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J} }[/math] would not be minimal with [math]\displaystyle{ \bigvee \mathcal{J} = 1 }[/math].
Now consider the weight function [math]\displaystyle{ w:\mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J}\to\mathbb{N} }[/math] given by [math]\displaystyle{ w(\mathcal{I}) := |\phi^{-1}(\mathcal{I})| }[/math]. We know [math]\displaystyle{ w(\mathcal{I})\geq 1 }[/math] by surjectivity, and moreover [math]\displaystyle{ w(\mathcal{J}) = 1 }[/math] by the assumption on [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J} }[/math]. Since the abundance of each [math]\displaystyle{ J\in\mathcal{J} }[/math] in [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] coincides with its [math]\displaystyle{ w }[/math]-abundance in [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J} }[/math], it is enough to derive a suitable bound on the [math]\displaystyle{ w }[/math]-abundance.
[math]\displaystyle{ w\geq 1 }[/math] already fixes the distribution of a total weight of [math]\displaystyle{ 2^{|J|} }[/math]. For the remaining weight of [math]\displaystyle{ n-2^{|J|} }[/math], the worst-case scenario is that it is completely concentrated on the coatoms of [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{B}_J }[/math]. (And this can indeed happen.) Since every [math]\displaystyle{ J\in\mathcal{J} }[/math] is contained in all but one coatoms, the pigeonhole principle guarantees that there is [math]\displaystyle{ J }[/math] whose abundance with respect to the remaining weight is at most [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|} }[/math]. This means that its total abundance is at most [math]\displaystyle{ 2^{|J|-1} + \frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|} }[/math], as was to be shown.
Corollary: Suppose that [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] contains a maximal chain of length [math]\displaystyle{ c }[/math]. Then there is a join-irreducible element of abundance at most [math]\displaystyle{ n - \frac{n-1}{c-1} }[/math].
Proof: If the maximal chain is [math]\displaystyle{ 0=A_1\subseteq A_2\subseteq\ldots\subseteq A_c = 1 }[/math], then write [math]\displaystyle{ A_{k+1} = A_k\lor J_k }[/math] for join-irreducible [math]\displaystyle{ J_k }[/math]. Then [math]\displaystyle{ \bigvee_k J_k = 1 }[/math], and choose a minimal subset of the [math]\displaystyle{ J_k }[/math]'s with this property.
Case 2: Equal maximal chains
The opposite extreme is that all maximal chains have equal length, i.e. that [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] satisfies the Jordan-Dedekind chain condition. In this case, [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] is graded. We distinguish two subcases depending on the height [math]\displaystyle{ h }[/math] and the width [math]\displaystyle{ w }[/math]; since [math]\displaystyle{ (h-1)(w-1)\geq n-1 }[/math], they can't both be too small. Using the JD chain condition, do arguments along the lines of Dilworth's theorem or Mirsky's theorem give more information?
Case 2a: large height
The height of [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] can be at most [math]\displaystyle{ h=m+1 }[/math]. If this value is reached, then [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] has a prime element by the dual of Theorem 15 in this paper, and we are done since every prime element is rare.
Case 2b: large width
In this case, can try to choose a large maximal antichain and a join-irreducible element [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math] such that [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A}_x }[/math] contains as few elements of the antichain as possible.