Carlson-Simpson theorem: Difference between revisions

From Polymath Wiki
Jump to navigationJump to search
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Carlson-Simpson theorem''' (k=3): If <math>[3]^\omega := \bigcup_{n=0}^\infty [3]^n</math> is partitioned into finitely many color classes, then one of the color classes contains an infinite-dimensional combinatorial subspace, i.e. another copy of <math>[3]^\omega</math>.
'''Carlson-Simpson theorem''' (k=3): If <math>[3]^\omega := \bigcup_{n=0}^\infty [3]^n</math> is partitioned into finitely many color classes, then one of the color classes contains an infinite-dimensional [[combinatorial subspace]], i.e. another copy of <math>[3]^\omega</math>.


Implies the [[coloring Hales-Jewett theorem]].  The k=2 version already implies Hindman's theorem.
Implies the [[coloring Hales-Jewett theorem]].  The k=2 version already implies [[Hindman's theorem]].


It is used in the [[Furstenberg-Katznelson argument]].
It is used in the [[Furstenberg-Katznelson argument]].

Revision as of 14:23, 15 February 2009

Carlson-Simpson theorem (k=3): If [math]\displaystyle{ [3]^\omega := \bigcup_{n=0}^\infty [3]^n }[/math] is partitioned into finitely many color classes, then one of the color classes contains an infinite-dimensional combinatorial subspace, i.e. another copy of [math]\displaystyle{ [3]^\omega }[/math].

Implies the coloring Hales-Jewett theorem. The k=2 version already implies Hindman's theorem.

It is used in the Furstenberg-Katznelson argument.