Lattice approach: Difference between revisions
TobiasFritz (talk | contribs) No edit summary |
TobiasFritz (talk | contribs) added Knill's argument |
||
Line 2: | Line 2: | ||
Throwing in a new atom below every join-irreducible creates a new lattice in which abundances differ by less than a factor of 2. So for the purposes of weak FUNC, it should be possible to assume wlog that <math>\mathcal{A}</math> is atomistic. | Throwing in a new atom below every join-irreducible creates a new lattice in which abundances differ by less than a factor of 2. So for the purposes of weak FUNC, it should be possible to assume wlog that <math>\mathcal{A}</math> is atomistic. | ||
== Knill's argument in lattice terms == | |||
The following is a lattice-theoretic formulation of a [https://gowers.wordpress.com/2016/02/08/func2-more-examples/#comment-154383 small tightening] of Knill's argument. | |||
'''Proposition:''' Let <math>\mathcal{J}\subseteq\mathcal{A}</math> be a set of join-irreducibles with <math>\bigvee \mathcal{J} = 1</math> and minimal with this property. Then some member of <math>\mathcal{J}</math> has abundance at most <math>2^{|J|-1} + \frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|}</math>. | |||
Note that at the two extreme values <math>|J|=2</math> or <math>|J|=\log_2(n)</math>, this establishes an element of abundance at most <math>1/2</math>. | |||
'''Proof:''' Let <math>\mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J}</math> be the Boolean algebra of subsets of the set <math>\mathcal{J}</math>. Consider the map <math>\phi:\mathcal{A}\to\mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J}</math> given by <math>\phi(A):=\{J\in \mathcal{J}\:|\: J\leq A\}</math>. We claim that <math>\phi</math> is surjective. Indeed, for every <math>\mathcal{I}\subseteq\mathcal{J}</math> we have <math>\phi\left(\bigvee \mathcal{I}\right) = \mathcal{I}</math>; for if <math>\phi\left(\bigvee \mathcal{I} \right)</math> was larger, then <math>\mathcal{J}</math> would not be minimal with <math>\bigvee \mathcal{J} = 1</math>. | |||
Now consider the weight function <math>w:\mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J}\to\mathbb{N}</math> given by <math>w(\mathcal{I}) := |\phi^{-1}(\mathcal{I})|</math>. We know <math>w(\mathcal{I})\geq 1</math> by surjectivity, and moreover <math>w(\mathcal{J}) = 1</math> by the assumption on <math>\mathcal{J}</math>. Since the abundance of each <math>J\in\mathcal{J}</math> in <math>\mathcal{A}</math> coincides with its <math>w</math>-abundance in <math>\mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J}</math>, it is enough to derive a suitable bound on the <math>w</math>-abundance. | |||
<math>w\geq 1</math> already fixes the distribution of a total weight of <math>2^{|J|}</math>. For the remaining weight of <math>n-2^{|J|}</math>, the worst-case scenario is that it is completely concentrated on the coatoms of <math>\mathcal{B}_J</math>. (And this [https://gowers.wordpress.com/2016/02/08/func2-more-examples/#comment-154419 can indeed happen].) Since every <math>J\in\mathcal{J}</math> is contained in all but one coatoms, the pigeonhole principle guarantees that there is <math>J</math> whose abundance with respect to the remaining weight is at most <math>\frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|}</math>. This means that its total abundance is at most <math>2^{|J|-1} + \frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|}</math>, as was to be shown. | |||
'''Corollary:''' Suppose that <math>\mathcal{A}</math> contains a maximal chain of length $c$. Then... | |||
'''Proof:''' | |||
== Case 1: Short maximal chains == | == Case 1: Short maximal chains == |
Revision as of 20:04, 10 March 2016
This is an approach to proving (weak) FUNC in the lattice formulation by distinguishing various regimes of lattices. Let [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] be a finite lattice containing [math]\displaystyle{ m }[/math] join-irreducibles, and write [math]\displaystyle{ n=|\mathcal{A}| }[/math].
Throwing in a new atom below every join-irreducible creates a new lattice in which abundances differ by less than a factor of 2. So for the purposes of weak FUNC, it should be possible to assume wlog that [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] is atomistic.
Knill's argument in lattice terms
The following is a lattice-theoretic formulation of a small tightening of Knill's argument.
Proposition: Let [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J}\subseteq\mathcal{A} }[/math] be a set of join-irreducibles with [math]\displaystyle{ \bigvee \mathcal{J} = 1 }[/math] and minimal with this property. Then some member of [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J} }[/math] has abundance at most [math]\displaystyle{ 2^{|J|-1} + \frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|} }[/math].
Note that at the two extreme values [math]\displaystyle{ |J|=2 }[/math] or [math]\displaystyle{ |J|=\log_2(n) }[/math], this establishes an element of abundance at most [math]\displaystyle{ 1/2 }[/math].
Proof: Let [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J} }[/math] be the Boolean algebra of subsets of the set [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J} }[/math]. Consider the map [math]\displaystyle{ \phi:\mathcal{A}\to\mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J} }[/math] given by [math]\displaystyle{ \phi(A):=\{J\in \mathcal{J}\:|\: J\leq A\} }[/math]. We claim that [math]\displaystyle{ \phi }[/math] is surjective. Indeed, for every [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{I}\subseteq\mathcal{J} }[/math] we have [math]\displaystyle{ \phi\left(\bigvee \mathcal{I}\right) = \mathcal{I} }[/math]; for if [math]\displaystyle{ \phi\left(\bigvee \mathcal{I} \right) }[/math] was larger, then [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J} }[/math] would not be minimal with [math]\displaystyle{ \bigvee \mathcal{J} = 1 }[/math].
Now consider the weight function [math]\displaystyle{ w:\mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J}\to\mathbb{N} }[/math] given by [math]\displaystyle{ w(\mathcal{I}) := |\phi^{-1}(\mathcal{I})| }[/math]. We know [math]\displaystyle{ w(\mathcal{I})\geq 1 }[/math] by surjectivity, and moreover [math]\displaystyle{ w(\mathcal{J}) = 1 }[/math] by the assumption on [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{J} }[/math]. Since the abundance of each [math]\displaystyle{ J\in\mathcal{J} }[/math] in [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] coincides with its [math]\displaystyle{ w }[/math]-abundance in [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{B}_\mathcal{J} }[/math], it is enough to derive a suitable bound on the [math]\displaystyle{ w }[/math]-abundance.
[math]\displaystyle{ w\geq 1 }[/math] already fixes the distribution of a total weight of [math]\displaystyle{ 2^{|J|} }[/math]. For the remaining weight of [math]\displaystyle{ n-2^{|J|} }[/math], the worst-case scenario is that it is completely concentrated on the coatoms of [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{B}_J }[/math]. (And this can indeed happen.) Since every [math]\displaystyle{ J\in\mathcal{J} }[/math] is contained in all but one coatoms, the pigeonhole principle guarantees that there is [math]\displaystyle{ J }[/math] whose abundance with respect to the remaining weight is at most [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|} }[/math]. This means that its total abundance is at most [math]\displaystyle{ 2^{|J|-1} + \frac{(|J|-1)(n-2^{|J|})}{|J|} }[/math], as was to be shown.
Corollary: Suppose that [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] contains a maximal chain of length $c$. Then...
Proof:
Case 1: Short maximal chains
If [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] has a maximal chain of sufficiently small length [math]\displaystyle{ l }[/math], then a Knill-type argument establishes the existence of a join-irreducible element with relative abundance of at most [math]\displaystyle{ 1-\frac{1}{l-1} }[/math].
Case 2: Equal maximal chains
The opposite extreme is that all maximal chains have equal length, i.e. that [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] satisfies the Jordan-Dedekind chain condition. In this case, [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] is graded. We distinguish two subcases depending on the height [math]\displaystyle{ h }[/math] and the width [math]\displaystyle{ w }[/math]; since [math]\displaystyle{ (h-1)(w-1)\geq n-1 }[/math], they can't both be too small. Using the JD chain condition, do arguments along the lines of Dilworth's theorem or Mirsky's theorem give more information?
Case 2a: large height
The height of [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] can be at most [math]\displaystyle{ h=m+1 }[/math]. If this value is reached, then [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A} }[/math] has a prime element by the dual of Theorem 15 in this paper, and we are done since every prime element is rare.
Case 2b: large width
In this case, can try to choose a large maximal antichain and a join-irreducible element [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math] such that [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{A}_x }[/math] contains as few elements of the antichain as possible.